SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS

0
245
Reading Time: 25 minutes

     
         Written by Nelson Amobi

                               PETER SINGER
Abstract: Many people believe that all human life is of equal value. Most of them
also believe that all human beings have a moral status superior to that of
nonhuman animals. But how are these beliefs to be defended? The mere difference
of species cannot in itself determine moral status. The most obvious candidate for
regarding human beings as having a higher moral status than animals is the
superior cognitive capacity of humans. People with profound mental retardation
pose a problem for this set of beliefs, because their cognitive capacities are not
superior to those of many animals. I argue that we should drop the belief in the
equal value of human life, replacing it with a graduated view that applies to
animals as well as to humans.
Keywords: speciesism, animals, disability, ethics, moral status.
Introduction
This essay derives from a talk presented at the conference ‘‘Cognitive
Disability: A Challenge to Moral Philosophy.’’1 As that title suggests,
cognitive disability does present a challenge to moral philosophy. I focus
here on the challenge it presents to views about moral status that are
widespread both among moral philosophers and in the wider community.
However, the reverse is also true: moral philosophy can and ought to
challenge how we think about people with cognitive disabilities and about
the value of human life. I want to enlarge the sphere of discussion, so that
we are looking not just at people with cognitive disabilities but also at the
way in which our thoughts about moral status relate to beings who do not
have the cognitive abilities that normal humans have. Although there is
among some who write on cognitive disability a strong aversion to
1 The conference was held at Stony Brook University in New York City in September
2008. I dedicate these thoughts to Harriet McBryde Johnson because my presentation at the
conference was the first time since she died that I spoke on issues of intellectual disability. In
recent years, while she lived, whenever I spoke or wrote about intellectual disability, I could
expect an e-mail from her telling me where I was wrong. Knowing that my work would
receive her sharp scrutiny was a spur to defending my views as well as I could. Sadly I’m not
going to hear from her this time.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
METAPHILOSOPHY
Vol. 40, Nos. 3–4, July 2009
0026-1068
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
comparing humans with nonhuman animals, these comparisons are
unavoidable if we are to clarify the basis of moral status.
Hence I begin with some examples of cognitive abilities that show
significant overlap between some nonhuman animals and some human
beings. I then discuss the widely accepted ethic of ‘‘the equal value
and dignity of all human life,’’ and the various grounds—religious,
speciesist, cognitive-ability-based, and ‘‘slippery slope’’—on which people
have attempted to support this ethic. I argue that this view of universal
and equal human dignity cannot be supported without a drastic revision
to aspects of our morality, which most people do not want to make. As an
alternative, I present a graduated view of the moral status of humans and
nonhuman animals.
Cognitive Abilities in Humans and Animals
Let us consider a few examples of the capacities and cognitive abilities of
nonhuman beings, with regard to IQ and language comprehension. I
specifically want to consider research done on great apes, border collies,
and grey parrots.
Great apes: Francine Patterson of the Gorilla Foundation claims that
the gorilla Koko scored between 70 and 95 on human IQ tests and
understands about a thousand signs. Though this finding is controversial,
there is a substantial amount of uncontroversial research suggesting that
many of the great apes, including gorillas, chimpanzees, bonobos, and
orangutans, can use human sign language and can develop a fair range of
comprehension.2 At least, it is clear that they understand a number of
signs, and they use a kind of structured syntax. The question of whether
or not we should call this ‘‘language’’ is not my concern here. What is
relevant for this discussion is comparisons with humans with cognitive
disabilities; the point being that if we raise the standard for language to
exclude the signs used by Koko, Kanzi, Washoe, Chantek, or some of the
other signing apes, then we would have to say that some humans at
profound and severe levels of cognitive disability don’t have language
either. We must keep a level playing field for comparisons between
species—in this case between some humans with cognitive disabilities
and great apes.
Dogs: There’s been some interesting recent work on dogs’ abilities to
recognize human spoken language. Border collies, when presented with a
collection of hundreds of different toys with different names, are able to
respond and fetch a particular named object. Tests have demonstrated
that they can comprehend two hundred to three hundred human words.3
2 See, for example, the essays in part 2 of Paola Cavalieri and Peter Singer, eds., The
Great Ape Project: Equality Beyond Humanity (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1994).
3 See the research by Juliane Kamiski and Sebastian Tempelmann, cited by Virginia
Morell in ‘‘Minds of Their Own,’’ National Geographic, March 2008.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
568 PETER SINGER
Grey parrots: Remarkable work was done by Irene Pepperberg with
Alex, an African grey parrot, who died recently. Alex grasped about a
hundred words; of course, parrots are actually grasping spoken human
language and responding to it in the same spoken language—no sign
language here. Alex—and this also goes for other grey parrots that are
being studied—was shown to be not just ‘‘parroting,’’ because he could
answer novel questions. Furthermore, his answers to the questions showed
a grasp of concepts. For example, if Alex was shown a yellow sphere and a
yellow cube and was then asked, ‘‘What’s the same?’’ he would answer,
‘‘Color.’’ When shown a red sphere and a yellow sphere and asked,
‘‘What’s the same?’’ Alex would say, ‘‘Shape.’’ So it seems clear that Alex
understood what was going on with these basic concepts, and he had
modest numerical ability as well, being able to count up to seven.4
Having considered these examples of nonhuman animal cognitive
ability, let’s look at some human beings with cognitive disabilities. I’m
focusing here on the very bottom of the range: those with profound mental
retardation, and I acknowledge that this is a very small percentage of
people with intellectual disabilities. In fact, the American Association for
Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities says it’s 1 percent. Other
statistics are available that vary slightly on this, but the point is not so
much how many human beings there are in this category but rather the fact
that there are some, for they form the basis on which I will later raise
arguments about claims that all human beings have a certain kind of moral
status. I recognize that for those with a particular concern for people with
cognitive disabilities, this may make what I’m saying less interesting
because I am going to make an argument that concerns the moral status
of human beings in general, as compared to nonhuman animals. There
may also be some who are working with people with disabilities or who are
caregivers or relatives of people with cognitive disabilities who will look at
my examples of severe and profound cognitive disability and say to
themselves that I am not discussing people who are like the people that
they work with or care for. I acknowledge, of course, that people with
cognitive disabilities are not easy to categorize. Obviously the issues are
different depending on the severity of the cognitive disabilities. But let me
reiterate that for the moment I have in mind those with profound mental
retardation as defined below, and the definition is not mine.
According to the American Association on Intellectual and Developmental
Disabilities, people with profound mental retardation
have an IQ range below 25;
will always require much supervision, though they may acquire
some self-help skills;
4 See Irene Pepperberg, The Alex Studies: Cognitive and Communicative Abilities of Grey
Parrots (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999).
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 569
have an ability to understand that exceeds their ability to speak;
may have little or no speech;
may be capable of following simple directions;
have no academic skills;
may be unable to perform any useful work, though with training
may be able to achieve a work-activity level of productivity;
may appear socially isolated and pay little attention to others except
as it relates to their own needs.5
Now let us think about nonhuman animals in terms of these capacities.
IQ: Some nonhuman animals, such as the gorilla Koko, have IQ
ranges significantly above 25.
Supervision: Animals don’t require much supervision—many of
them get on and always have got on with their lives perfectly well—
often better—without human interference.
Speech: It is generally true that nonhuman animals have little or no
speech, or what we would call speech, although, as we have seen,
there are exceptions.
Following simple directions: Many animals, including dogs, can
follow simple directions. Can they acquire skills? Dogs, horses,
dolphins, pigeons, and several other animals can be trained to
perform useful work. In fact, one of the reasons why it is thought
that border collies are good at following human commands is that
traditionally they have been bred to work with sheep and to
respond to commands to separate some sheep from others.
Social isolation: We are not the only social animals; there is clearly
a wide range of social mammals for whom sociability is very
important. All of the great apes, primates generally, dogs, and
many other nonhuman animals are social beings and develop in
society, respond to the needs of other beings in their group,
communicate with them, reciprocate certain kinds of behavior,
and so on.
Given that there are some humans who are profoundly mentally retarded
and have the characteristics listed above, it is clearly not the case that all
humans have cognitive ability above all nonhuman animals. On the
contrary, we have many nonhuman animals who are significantly above
some human beings in their level of cognitive ability: in particular, they
are above those with profound mental retardation. Our question is: What
ethical significance can we draw from this?
5 Quoted from Taskforce Independence, ‘‘Supported Accommodation for All Who Need
It: A Reality, Not a Dream,’’ available at www.nds.org.au/nsw/Conferences/2007annual/
papers/3.1b_Discussion%20Paper_Australia.doc. I have been unable to trace the original
source.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
570 PETER SINGER
The Equal Value of All Human Life?
Consider this statement by Pope John Paul II: ‘‘As far as the right to life is
concerned, every innocent human being is absolutely equal to all others.
. . . Before the moral norm which prohibits the direct taking of the life of
an innocent human being there are no privileges or exceptions for anyone.
It makes no difference whether one is the master of the world or the
‘poorest of the poor’ on the face of the earth. Before the demands of
morality we are all absolutely equal.’’6 This represents a widely held
ethical position, not merely the position of a religious leader or of
someone with a Christian or, more specifically, a Roman Catholic
viewpoint. It expresses a kind of ‘‘official morality’’ that is often applied
in statements about people with cognitive disabilities. Most people pay lip
service to it, though I’m not sure how many really hold it when it comes to
the crunch. I will argue that this doctrine cannot be sustained in the light
of the facts that I have been referring to—or at least not without a very
drastic revision to aspects of our morality, which most people don’t want
to make.
Here is the problem: Can we justify attributing equal value to all
human lives, while at the same time attributing to human life a value that
is superior to all animal life? Of course Pope John Paul II’s statement does
not say, ‘‘All human life is absolutely equal but all humans are superior to
animals,’’ but obviously that is implied by the statement, and by the fact
that while popes very frequently denounce abortion and euthanasia, no
pope has yet denounced the unnecessary killing of animals for food,
although such killing takes place on a vastly larger scale than abortion
and euthanasia. (The number of animals killed for food each year is in the
tens of billions, vastly greater than the entire human population of the
planet, and that does not include fish and other marine creatures.)
Clearly, Pope John Paul II and those who accept his position on this
issue think not only that all humans are equal to each other but also that
they are far superior to nonhuman animals. The philosophical problem is
whether we can justify that view.
In what follows, I briefly discuss three general attempts to ground such
a view, dividing them into three categories: religious, speciesist, and those
that depend on cognitive abilities.
Religious Grounds
As Pope John Paul II’s statement indicates, obviously there is a variety of
religious grounds upon which people might attempt to justify the doctrine
of both the equal worth of all human life and human superiority over
6 John Paul II, Evangelium Vitae, 1995.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 571
nonhuman animals. For example, religious grounds might include the
following:
1. We are made in the image of God, and animals are not.
2. God gave us dominion over animals.
3. We have immortal souls, and animals do not.
I do not think there is any good evidence for any of these claims. I regard
them all as false. Some people may believe that these are true claims. I
would argue, however, that even if they are true, such claims should not
be the basis of law or public policy in a society that is not based on a
religious creed or religious profession. The desirability of keeping church
and state separate is sufficient basis for saying that even those who accept
these religious claims should agree that in a pluralist society they should
not suffice for making laws that regulate how we treat human beings and
nonhuman animals.
Speciesist Grounds
I use the term ‘‘speciesism’’ deliberately, to make a parallel with other
‘‘isms’’ that we are familiar with, particularly racism and sexism. There
are a number of arguments that fall into this general category. Sometimes
they are made by quite respectable philosophers—for example, Bernard
Williams, who defends the view that since we humans are doing the
judging, we are entitled to prefer our own kind.7 In response to an
example in his article about an imaginary situation in which humans are
being conquered by aliens, and the aliens defend their conquest by
claiming, truthfully, that they are intellectually superior to us and have
better, richer, and fuller lives than we do, Williams replies that if any
human accepted such an argument, we could respond by saying simply,
‘‘Whose side are you on?’’ Williams then applies this to the case of
animals, arguing that we are entitled simply to say, ‘‘We’re humans here,
we’re the ones doing the judging; you can’t really expect anything else but
a bias or prejudice in favor of human beings.’’ This seems to me to be a
very dangerous way to argue, precisely because of the parallel to which I
adverted above. I do not see that the argument is really different from a
white racist saying, when it comes to a question about how one should
treat people of different races, ‘‘Well, whose side are you on? We’re the
ones doing the judging here, why don’t we simply prefer our kind because
it is our kind?’’
We cannot claim that biological commonality entitles us to superior
status over those who are not members of our species. In the case of
7 Bernard Williams, ‘‘The Human Prejudice,’’ which appears, along with a response from
me, in Peter Singer Under Fire, edited by Jeffrey Schaler (Chicago: Open Court, forthcoming).
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
572 PETER SINGER
applying this to people with severe and profound cognitive disabilities,
there is also a problem about saying who the ‘‘we’’ are. What is really
important about saying ‘‘us?’’ Is it that we are all capable of understanding
language, and perhaps even rational argument? In that case, I
am not addressing those who are profoundly mentally retarded. Or is it
that I am addressing all those who are members of my species? I think it is
much more important that the ‘‘we’’ of this statement are beings of at
least a certain level of cognitive ability. So, if it happens that one of you is
an alien who has cleverly disguised yourself in a human shape, but you are
capable of understanding this argument, I am talking to you just as I am
talking to members of my own species. In important respects, I have
much more in common with you than I do with someone who is of my
species but, because he or she is profoundly mentally retarded, has no
capacity for verbal communication with me at all. In other words, if we
take Williams’s question ‘‘Whose side are you on?’’ to refer to being on
the side of those who share our species membership (as he presumably
intended it), it is a bad argument. If on the other hand we take it to refer
to being on the side of those capable of sharing in discussions of right and
wrong, it clearly does not support the claim that all humans are equal.
There is another claim that one often hears: that humans and no others
have intrinsic worth and dignity, and that is why humans have superior
status. This is really just a piece of rhetoric unless it is given some support.
What is it about human beings that gives them moral worth and dignity?
If there is no good answer forthcoming, this talk of intrinsic worth and
dignity is just speciesism in nicer terms. I do not see any argument in the
claim that merely being a member of the species Homo sapiens gives you
moral worth and dignity, whereas being a member of the species Pan
troglodytes (chimpanzees) does not give you worth and dignity. Something
more would need to be said.
Superior Cognitive Abilities
Some have attempted to justify superior moral status for humans on the
basis that humans have superior cognitive abilities. Many people refer to
Immanuel Kant’s moral philosophy as providing justification for the
claims that human beings are ends in themselves, and that humans have
both worth and dignity, while animals do not. In Kant’s view, ‘‘Animals
are not self-conscious and are there merely as a means to an end. That end
is man.’’8 Kant’s argument for why human beings are ends-in-themselves
is that they are autonomous beings, which, in terms of Kantian philosophy,
means that they are capable of reasoning. Note that Kant goes from
defending the value of autonomy or self-consciousness to maintaining
8 Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics, translated by Louis Infield (New York: Harper
Torchbooks, 1963), p. 239.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 573
that ‘‘man’’ is the end. If we really take his argument seriously it means
that human beings who are not self-conscious—because perhaps they are
so profoundly mentally retarded that they lack self-consciousness or selfawareness—
are also merely means to an end, that end being autonomous
or self-conscious beings. So the Kantian approach is not going to help
those whose objective is to demonstrate that all human beings have
superior status to nonhuman animals.
Those who see morality as a social contract are also likely to link moral
status to higher cognitive capacities. According to this view, the core of
morality is that I agree not to harm you, in return for your agreement not
to harm me.9 Some cognitive abilities are required to be capable of
forming and adhering to an agreement of this kind. If you are profoundly
mentally retarded, you may not have those abilities. You certainly are not
likely to have them to an extent that is superior to that of some
nonhuman animals, who have been shown to be capable of reciprocity.
As with the Kantian argument, therefore, a contractarian account of
morality is unable to justify granting all humans a moral status superior
to that of any nonhuman animal, though it may justify granting some
humans a moral status superior to that of some humans and of any
nonhuman animal.
So to reiterate: because of the overlap in cognitive ability between
some humans and some nonhuman animals, attempts to draw a moral
line on the basis of cognitive ability, as Kant and the contractarians try to
do, will require either that we exclude some humans—for example, those
who are profoundly mentally retarded—or that we include some nonhuman
animals—those whose levels of cognitive ability are equal or superior
to the lowest level found in human beings. Hence we have to conclude
that the standard ethical view that we find expressed in the statement by
John Paul II—the view that all human beings, irrespective of their
cognitive abilities, have equal moral status, and that this status is superior
to the moral status of the most intelligent nonhuman animals—cannot be
defended. We find ourselves in need of an alternative to the status quo.
An Alternative View
There are a number of possible alternatives to the view that all human life
is of equal value, and this value is superior to that of any nonhuman
animals. We could:
1. preserve equality by raising the status of animals, granting them the
same status we now grant to humans; or
9 The social contract view can be found in ancient Greece, for example in the position of
Glaucon, as represented in Plato’s Republic. Its most famous exponents are Thomas Hobbes,
John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and in our own era, John Rawls and David
Gauthier.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
574 PETER SINGER
2. preserve equality by lowering the status of humans to that which we
now grant to animals; or
3. abandon the idea of the equal value of all humans, replacing that
with a more graduated view in which moral status depends on some
aspects of cognitive ability, and that graduated view is applied both
to humans and nonhumans.
I assume that we can all agree in rejecting (2). I am to some extent
sympathetic to (1) but not in every respect. Alternative (3) remains a
possibility; let us consider how we might go in that direction.
Long before most people were contemplating any serious degree of
concern for animals, Jeremy Bentham, the founding father of the English
school of Utilitarianism, wrote, ‘‘The question is not, ‘Can they reason?’
nor, ‘Can they talk?’ but, ‘Can they suffer?’’’10 That is indeed a crucial
question to ask whenever we are talking about beings who are capable of
suffering and one that is clearly relevant to how we should treat both
humans and nonhuman animals. Can they suffer? Can they enjoy life? If
so, they have interests that we should take into account, and we should
give those interests equal weight with the interests of all other beings with
similar interests. We should not discount their interests in not suffering
because they cannot talk or because they are incapable of reasoning; and
we should not discount their interests in enjoying life, in having things
that are fulfilling and rewarding for them, either. The principle of equal
consideration of interests should apply to both humans and animals.
That’s the sense in which I want to elevate animals to the moral status of
humans.
I imagine that many people who care for profoundly mentally retarded
humans would support Bentham’s idea that the ability to talk or to
reason is irrelevant to the importance of avoiding suffering and facilitating
an enjoyable life. But Bentham’s principle many not apply to all
aspects of human or animal life. Consider a comment from Roger
Scruton, a conservative British philosopher who defends the killing and
eating of animals, although only if they are well treated during their life
and not, for example, reared on modern intensive farms. Killing animals
is not, Scruton says, wrong in itself, because ‘‘there is a real distinction,
for a human being, between timely and untimely death. To be ‘cut short’
before one’s time is a waste—even a tragedy. . . . No such thoughts apply
to domestic cattle. To be killed at thirty months is not intrinsically more
tragic than to be killed at forty, fifty, or sixty.’’11
One of the reasons Scruton thinks that ‘‘untimely death’’ is a tragedy
for a human being is that if a human being is killed before his or her time
10 Jeremy Bentham, Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789),
chap. 17.
11 Roger Scruton, ‘‘The Conscientious Carnivore,’’ in Food for Thought, edited by Steve
Sapntzis (Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus, 2004), pp. 81–91; the passage quoted is on p. 88.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 575
there are likely to be achievements that this human being may have
accomplished which he or she will not accomplish. So, if you like, there is
a failure to carry out plans that had been made, and to achieve what the
person wanted to achieve. Cattle, on Scruton’s view, have no plans for the
future, and no accomplishments that they would have achieved, had they
been able to live long longer. We could debate this factual claim, but I
accept the normative view that there is greater significance in killing a
being who has plans for the future—who wishes to accomplish things—
than there is in killing a being who is incapable of thinking about the
future at all but exists either moment to moment or within a very shorttime
horizon (for example, a time horizon limited to thinking about
eating something in the near future). It is, other things being equal, much
less a tragedy to kill that sort of being than to kill someone who wants to
live long enough to do the sorts of things that humans typically want to
achieve over the course of their lives. But, of course, if this reason is
invoked to justify killing well-treated animals for food, then this has
implications for the question of whether one can justify ending the life of
a profoundly cognitively disabled human being. One could, after all,
rewrite Scruton’s statement as follows: ‘‘There is a real distinction, for a
cognitively normal human being, between timely and untimely death. To
be ‘cut short’ before one’s time is a waste—even a tragedy. . . . No such
thoughts apply to a being unable to make plans for the future. For such a
being, to be killed at an early age is not intrinsically more tragic than to
die in old age.’’ Of course, this challenges a widely accepted human ethic.
So if you thought that Scruton provided you with a sound justification for
continuing to enjoy steak for dinner (as long as you get humanely raised,
grass-bred beef), you need to think whether you are prepared to accept
the argument in a nonspeciesist way and apply it to all beings who are
unable to make plans for the future.
That there is some significance, as far as the wrongness of killing is
concerned, in whether the being killed can think about the future, seems
to me defensible. How much significance there is in this is a more difficult
question, to which I have no clear answer. But I think we can conclude
that pain and suffering are equally bad—and pleasure and happiness
equally good—whether the being experiencing them is human or nonhuman,
rational or nonrational, capable of discourse or not. On the other
hand, death is a greater or lesser loss depending on factors like the extent
to which the being was aware of his or her existence over time, and of
course the quality of life the being was likely to have, had it continued to
live.
The Views of Parents
The parents of children with cognitive disabilities differ greatly in their
attitudes to their children. Consider some comments parents have made
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
576 PETER SINGER
about children born with disabilities considerably less severe than those I
have been considering. Here is a highly positive view:
Those of us with a Down’s Syndrome child (our son, Robert, is almost 24)
often wish that all our children had this extraordinary syndrome which defeats
anger and malice, replacing them with humor, thoughtfulness and devotion
to friends and family.12
And here is one of the contrary opinions that I’ve had expressed to me:
My son, John [not his real name] was born almost 2 1
2 years ago 11 weeks
premature and weighing only 1 lb. 14 oz. . . . John has spastic diplegia cerebral
palsy with underlying right hemiplegia. . ., has sensory problems, and has
speech delays. . . . My husband and I love our son (middle of three), but had
someone told me, ‘‘Mrs B. your son will have numerous disabilities down the
road. Do you still want us to intubate him?,’’ my answer would have been no.
It would have been a gut wrenching decision, but it would have been for the
best. It would have been in the best interest for John, for us, and for our
children. I am saddened beyond words to think of all he will have to cope with
as he grows older.13
I don’t have enough data to venture a conclusion as to which view is the
more prevalent among parents of children with disabilities, and even if I
did, that would not resolve the ethical question one way or another.
Rather, we should consider parental choice as a factor in its own right,
and one that ought to have an important role in decisions about whether
to prolong life or whether to end it. (I would add here that if the parents
of John would have been justified in refusing life-prolonging treatment
shortly after his birth, then in my view they would also have been justified
in taking active steps to end his life at a later stage, if they still believed
that that was in his best interests, and he was incapable of expressing any
view on such a matter.)
Who Has Dignity?
Before closing, I will comment briefly on a case that received extensive
publicity in 2007. At the time of the procedure I am about to describe,
Ashley was a nine-year-old girl living with her family in Seattle. There was
some dispute about how profound her disabilities were. It was reported
that she was unable to walk or talk, keep her head up, roll over, or sit up
by herself; that she was fed with a tube, and that she could not swallow.
After discussion with her parents, doctors administered hormones to
prevent normal growth. The aim of this growth attenuation was to keep
12 Quoted from Ann Bradley, ‘‘Why Shouldn’t Women Abort Disabled Fetuses?’’ Living
Marxism 82 (Sept. 1995).
13 From a letter sent to me in 1999 after publicity about my views on euthanasia for
severely disabled infants (name withheld).
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 577
Ashley small and make her easier to care for. The parents said that this
was in Ashley’s interests, as it would make it possible for her to continue
to travel with the family on vacation. Ashley’s doctors also, again in
accordance with her parents’ wishes, performed a hysterectomy and
removed her breast buds—the hysterectomy so that she would not have
problems with menstruation, and the breast bud removal, they said, once
again to keep her lighter and easier to care for, but also to reduce the
likelihood that if she had to be placed in an institution, she would be a
victim of sexual assault.
During the controversy that arose after Ashley’s treatment was
publicized, an article in the Los Angeles Times said: ‘‘This is about
Ashley’s dignity. Everybody examining her case seems to agree about
that.’’14 But ‘‘dignity’’ is a vague term. We are prepared to use the term
‘‘best interests’’ for animals without too much hesitation; we know what
that means. We are less willing to speak of an animal’s dignity, because it
is not clear what cognitive capacities might be required for a being to have
dignity. The same problem arises for someone as developmentally
disabled as Ashley. It isn’t clear how she could possess dignity. If we
say that she does, are we also prepared to grant dignity to nonhuman
animals at a similar cognitive level?
In my view, whether the treatment to which Ashley was subjected was
justifiable depends primarily on whether it was in her best interests, rather
than whether it befitted her dignity.
‘‘Slippery Slope’’ Arguments
Some people may object that even if the position I am taking is
completely logical, in the abstract, it is nevertheless dangerous in the
real world, because it leads to a slippery slope. We should, these people
are likely to say, affirm the dignity and worth of the human person
precisely because in the past century we’ve come through the scourge of
wars and genocides that have been based on failure to respect human
dignity and worth. So the question arises: Even if it is not philosophically
defensible by any other means, is it still sound policy to maintain that all
human beings have dignity and worth, in order to avoid a recurrence of
the tragedies that occurred during the Nazi era and afterward?
This so-called slippery slope argument is often made specifically with
regard to the need to protect the status of those with intellectual
disabilities. For example, a fact sheet from the American Association
on Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities refers to the ‘‘long history
of oppression and the callous disregard for the lives of individuals with
mental retardation’’ and offers this as a reason why we ‘‘must be
14 Sam Verhovek, ‘‘Parents Defend Decision to Keep Disabled Girl Small,’’ Los Angeles
Times January 3, 2007.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
578 PETER SINGER
especially vigilant to protect the autonomy and the right to equal
protection under the law of individuals with mental retardation.’’ I agree
that there has been a long history of oppression and callous disregard for
the lives of individuals with mental retardation.15 I also agree that we
should do our best to avoid such oppression and callous disregard.
But should we accept the slippery slope argument as a reason for not
making any changes in the ethic that we currently have? Here we need to
ask some questions. First, in terms of the danger of a repeat of the
Holocaust, how significant are the particular historical circumstances in
which those events took place? That is a question we can debate, a
historical question as to whether we are likely to go down that slope
again, given very different historical circumstances. But second and very
important, if it is only the slippery slope argument that justifies our talk
about the equal value of all human life, what is the cost of maintaining
this fiction?
One cost of adhering to the slippery slope argument is the cost to
nonhuman animals of the continuation of the view that they are inferior
in moral status to all human beings. If we are moved by pictures of
institutionalized and physically confined children with intellectual disabilities,
as we should be,16 then surely we should be equally moved by
photographs of animals on factory farms, kept in even closer confinement—
especially when we know that the latter situation, but not the
former, is still the rule in the United States. For example, the breeding
sows that produce almost all of the pork, bacon, and ham sold in this
country are so tightly confined in metal crates that they cannot walk a
single step or turn around. And yet, pigs are animals who compare quite
well in terms of cognitive abilities with human beings who are profoundly
mentally retarded. I doubt that it would be possible for people to treat
pigs in this way, if they did not put them in a moral category that is far
inferior to that in which they would place any human being. For hundreds
of millions of sentient beings, the cost of the barrier that we draw between
human and nonhuman animals is immense.
The other cost involved in maintaining the belief in the equal value of
all human life falls on those parents who feel like John’s mother, whom I
quoted above. If some parents believe that it is in the best interests of their
profoundly mentally retarded child and of their family that their child
should not live, then they should not be compelled, because it is
important for us all to maintain the fiction that every human life is of
equal value, to accept medical treatment for their child in order to make
that child live, and in some circumstances—especially if the child is
15 This was amply documented in Douglas Biklen’s presentation at the conference at
which the original version of this essay was presented.
16 I am referring here to a photograph that Dr. Biklen showed of a child confined in a cot
that looked more like a cage.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 579
suffering—they should have the option of euthanasia to end the child’s
life. To force the parents to bring up the child, neither for their own
benefit nor for the benefit of the child but so that we do not slide down an
allegedly possible slippery slope into a repetition of the Holocaust, is,
ironically, to do just what Kantians normally object to doing: treating the
child (and the parents) as merely a means to an end. The cost, financial,
physical, and emotional, of bringing up a profoundly mentally retarded
child is great even when parents positively want to bring up their child. It
will clearly be much harder to bear if the parents never wanted to bring up
the child but were not able to make that choice.
In any case, is it even possible, in the long run, to maintain the ethical
stance that is supposed to prevent us sliding down the slippery slope? I
mentioned above that this idea of the equal value of all human life is part
of ‘‘official’’ morality. Then I added a qualification: it’s the morality
we pay lip service to. If we look at what people do, when they have a
choice, as distinct from what they say, we can see that the idea that all life
is of equal value is not the morality that people in fact act on. Consider
pregnant women who are told their child will have a cognitive disability—
and of course the cognitive disability that most pregnant women are told
about is a relatively mild one, Down syndrome. And yet we know that
85 percent of the women who are told that their fetus carries the extra
chromosome that causes Down syndrome elect to terminate the pregnancy.
Presumably for women who are told that the child would have a
more severe form of mental retardation, that number is, if anything, still
higher. So when it comes to making choices for what kind of child we
want to have, very few among us believe that all human lives are equally
worth having, and that it doesn’t really matter what level of cognitive
ability your child will have. Most of us prefer to have a child with normal
cognitive abilities when we have that choice.When it comes to the crunch,
the fiction that we believe in the equal value of all human life breaks
down, here as in other areas of life-and-death decision making.17
There is also the question of allowing severely disabled infants to die.
In many hospitals—perhaps most hospitals today—this is, in certain
cases, a part of normal practice. I sometimes take my Princeton students
to the nearest neonatal intensive care unit, which happens to be a Catholic
hospital—Saint Peter’s Hospital in New Brunswick, New Jersey. When
we are there, the director of that neonatal intensive unit is prepared to tell
my students quite openly—he has done it with a video camera rolling in
front of him, and in front of the hospital’s Catholic chaplain as well—that
there are some cases where he withdraws treatment and allows a baby to
die. If an extremely premature baby is on a respirator and has had a
massive bleeding in the brain, and the physicians agree that the child is
17 For discussion of other areas, see Peter Singer, Rethinking Life and Death (New York:
St. Martin’s Press, 1995).
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
580 PETER SINGER
going to be so cognitively disabled as to be unable to do anything but lie
in bed without responding to his or her parents, the director will suggest
to the parents that treatment be withdrawn. The parents almost always
accept that suggestion, and the baby dies. So even in a Catholic hospital
decisions about life and death are not really based on the equal value of
all human life.
Conclusion
In closing, let me say that I am aware that this is a large topic, and I make
no claim to be expert on all aspects of it. I hope I have nevertheless said
enough to challenge two closely related views: that species membership is
crucial to moral status, and that all human life is of equal value. If I am
right, this makes a difference to the ethical options available to us when
we consider decisions we are called upon to make for those who are
profoundly mentally retarded.
University Center for Human Values
Princeton University
Princeton, NJ 08544
USA
and
Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics
University of Melbourne,
Parkville, Victoria
Australia 3010
psinger@princeton.edu
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 581